The Unapologetic Mathematician

Mathematics for the interested outsider

Free products of groups

On Tuesday I talked about how to put a group structure on the Cartesian product of two groups, and showed that it satisfied a universal property. For free products I’m just going to start from the property. First, the picture.

Universal Property of Coproducts

This is the same diagram as before, but now it’s upside-down. All the arrows run the other way. So we read this property as follows: Given two groups G and H, the free product is a group G*H with homomorphisms \iota_G:G\rightarrow G*H and \iota_H:H\rightarrow G*H so that given any other group X with homomorphisms f_G:G\rightarrow X and f_H:H\rightarrow X there is a unique homomorphism f_G*f_H:G*H\rightarrow X.

The exact same argument from Tuesday shows that if there is any such group G*H, it is uniquely determined up to isomorphism. What we need is to have an example of a group satisfying this property.

First of all, \iota_G has to be an monomorphism. Just put G itself for X, the identity on G for f_G, and the trivial homomorphism (sending everything to the identity) for f_H. Now anything in the kernel of \iota_G is automatically in the kernel of the composition of \iota_G with the coproduct map. But this composite is the identity homomorphism on G, which has trivial kernel, and so must \iota_G. This means that a copy of G must sit inside G*H. Similarly a copy of H must sit inside G*H.

So how do those two copies interact? Let’s put F_2 in for X and let f_G send everything in G to some power of the generator a — effectively defining a homomorphism from G to F_1\cong\mathbb{Z} — while f_H sends everything in H to some power of the generator b. If there’s any relation between the copies of G and H sitting inside G*H, it won’t be respected by the function to F_2 required by the universal property. So there can’t be any such relation.

G*H is actually very much like F_2, only instead of alternating powers of a and b, we have alternating members of G and H. An arbitrary element looks something like g_1h_1g_2h_2...g_kh_k. Of course it could start with an element of H or end with an element of G. The important thing is that the entries from the two groups alternate. We compose by just sticking sequences together like for a free group. If one sequence ends with an element of G and the next sequence starts with an element of G, we compose those elements in G so the whole sequence is still alternating.

Does G sit inside here? Of course! It’s just sequences with only an element of G in them. The same goes for H. And given any group X and homomorphisms f_G and f_H, we can send g_1h_1g_2h_2...g_k to f_G(g_1)f_H(h_1)f_G(g_2)f_H(h_2)...f_G(g_k). That’s our f_G*f_H. As I said above, any other group that has this property is isomorphic to G*H, so we’re done.

If we compare the free product G*H with the direct product G\times H, we see that the main difference is that elements of G and H don’t commute inside G*H, but they do inside G\times H. We can check that (g,e_H)(e_G,h)=(ge_G,e_Hh)=(g,h)=(e_Gg,he_H)=(e_G,h)(g,e_H). In fact, take a presentation of G with generators X and relations R, and one of H with generators Y and relations S, and with X and Y sharing no elements. Then G*H has generators X\cup Y and relations R\cup S, while G\times H has generators X\cup Y and relations R\cup S\cup\{xyx^{-1}y^{-1} (x\in X, y\in Y)\}.

Since we’ve only added some relations to the presentation to get from G*H to G\times H, the latter group is a quotient of the former. There should be some epimorphism from G*H to G\times H. I’ll leave it to you to show that some such epimorphism does exist in two ways: once by the universal property of G*H and once by the universal property of G\times H.

March 1, 2007 - Posted by | Algebra, Group theory, Structure of Groups, Universal Properties

6 Comments »

  1. […] of diagrams. Check that in this property is satisfied by disjoint unions. In coproducts are free products. In a preorder, coproducts are least upper bounds. And, of course, the coproduct defines a functor […]

    Pingback by Products and Coproducts « The Unapologetic Mathematician | December 5, 2007 | Reply

  2. I thought the free product of groups did not necessarily yield a group. I read somewhere that the free product Z(2)*Z(2)(Z(2) = integers mod 2) is not a group. This was in the context of defining the free product from the “bottom up” – strings of representatives with concatenation and reduction. Does that give the same result as your top down method with morphisms etc?

    Comment by GK | February 20, 2011 | Reply

  3. Sorry. I was confusing free products of groups with free groups. Dnnnng!

    Comment by GK | February 20, 2011 | Reply

  4. Right: the product of free groups isn’t a free group. But the free product of free groups is a free group.

    Comment by John Armstrong | February 20, 2011 | Reply

  5. “Let’s put F_2 in for X and let f_G send everything in G to the generator a, while f_H sends everything in H to the generator b.”

    Surely, then, f_G and f_H are not group homomorphisms? If we have an element g in G, by your definition we have f_G(g) = a, and f_G(g^2) = a, but we should have f_G(g^2) = a^2, which is not equal to a. Also, we can’t map the identity in G to a either. Similarly for H.

    Comment by TC | May 29, 2012 | Reply

  6. Good catch, TC; I was overly glib there. Really I was thinking of sending everything to some expression in F_2 involving only one of the generators.

    Comment by John Armstrong | May 29, 2012 | Reply


Leave a reply to Products and Coproducts « The Unapologetic Mathematician Cancel reply