The Unapologetic Mathematician

Mathematics for the interested outsider

Proving the Classification Theorem I

This week, we will prove the classification theorem for root systems. The proof consist of a long series of steps, and we’ll split it up over a number of posts.

Our strategy is to determine which Coxeter graphs can arise from actual root systems, and then see what Dynkin diagrams we can get. Since Coxeter graphs ignore relative lengths of roots, we will start by just working with unit vectors whose pairwise angles are described by the Coxeter graph.

So, for the time being we make the following assumptions: V is a real inner-product space (of arbitrary dimension), and \mathfrak{D}=\{\epsilon_1,\dots,\epsilon_n\} is a set of n linearly independent unit vectors satisfying \langle\epsilon_i,\epsilon_j\rangle\leq0 and 4\langle\epsilon_i,\epsilon_j\rangle^2 is one of 0, 1, 2, or 3 for i\neq j. For the duration of this proof, we will call such a set of vectors “admissible”. The elements of a base \Delta for a root system \Phi, divided by their lengths, are an admissible set.

We construct a Coxeter graph \Gamma, just as before, for every admissible set, and these clearly include the Coxeter graphs that come from root systems. Our task is now to classify all the connected Coxeter graphs that come from admissible sets of vectors.

  1. If we remove some of the vectors from an admissible set, then the remaining vectors still form an admissible set. The Coxeter graph of the new set is obtained from that of the old one by removing the vertices corresponding to the removed vectors and all their incident edges.
  2. This should be straightforward. The remaining vectors are still linearly independent, and they still have unit length. The angles between each pair are also unchanged. All we do is remove some vectors (vertices in the graph).

  3. The number of pairs of vertices in \Gamma connected by at least one edge is strictly less than n — the number of overall vertices.
  4. Let us define

    \displaystyle\epsilon=\sum\limits_{i=1}^n\epsilon_i

    Since the \epsilon_i are linearly independent, \epsilon cannot be zero. Thus we find that

    \displaystyle\begin{aligned}0<\langle\epsilon,\epsilon\rangle&=\left\langle\sum\limits_{i=1}^n\epsilon_i,\sum\limits_{j=1}^n\epsilon_j\right\rangle\\&=\sum\limits_{i=1}^n\sum\limits_{j=1}^n\langle\epsilon_i,\epsilon_j\rangle\\&=\sum\limits_{i<j}\langle\epsilon_i,\epsilon_j\rangle+\sum\limits_{i=j}\langle\epsilon_i,\epsilon_j\rangle+\sum\limits_{i>j}\langle\epsilon_i,\epsilon_j\rangle\\&=n+2\sum\limits_{i<j}\langle\epsilon_i,\epsilon_j\rangle\end{aligned}

    Now, for any pair \epsilon_i and \epsilon_j joined by an edge, we must find that 4\langle\epsilon_i,\epsilon_j\rangle^2 is 1, 2, or 3, and thus that 2\langle\epsilon_i,\epsilon_j\rangle\leq-1. Clearly, we can have no more than n-1 of these edges if we are to satisfy the above inequality.

  5. The graph \Gamma contains no cycles
  6. Indeed, if we have a cycle of length n in the graph, we could (using our step 1) discard all the vertices not involved in the cycle and still have the graph of an admissible set. But this graph would have n vertices and at least n edges — the ones involved in the cycle. But this is is impossible by step 2!

February 22, 2010 - Posted by | Geometry, Root Systems

8 Comments »

  1. Hi – I think you missed out a minus sign in step two, near the end: 2\langle\epsilon_i,\epsilon_j\rangle\leq1.
    Paul

    Comment by Paul Scriven | February 23, 2010 | Reply

  2. Ah yes, thanks.

    Comment by John Armstrong | February 23, 2010 | Reply

  3. […] Proving the Classification Theorem II We continue with the proof of the classification theorem that we started yesterday. […]

    Pingback by Proving the Classification Theorem II « The Unapologetic Mathematician | February 23, 2010 | Reply

  4. Students love to have a Big Theorem at the end of the semester, from which mountaintop to survey the landscape that they have mastered. This classification result is such a theorem.

    Comment by Jonathan Vos Post | February 23, 2010 | Reply

  5. Well it’s not done yet. After proving what was stated on Friday, we have to actually show whether or not any of these possible diagrams actually do occur.

    Comment by John Armstrong | February 23, 2010 | Reply

  6. […] continue with the proof of the classification theorem. The first two parts are here and […]

    Pingback by Proving the Classification Theorem III « The Unapologetic Mathematician | February 25, 2010 | Reply

  7. […] Theorem IV We continue proving the classification theorem. The first three parts are here, here, and […]

    Pingback by Proving the Classification Theorem IV « The Unapologetic Mathematician | February 25, 2010 | Reply

  8. […] Today we conclude the proof of the classification theorem. The first four parts of the proof are here, here, here, and […]

    Pingback by Proving the Classification Theorem V « The Unapologetic Mathematician | February 26, 2010 | Reply


Leave a comment