The Unapologetic Mathematician

Mathematics for the interested outsider

Direct Products of Groups

There are two sorts of products on groups that I’d like to discuss. Today I’ll talk about direct products.

The direct product says that we can take two groups, form the Cartesian product of their sets, and put the structure of a group on that. Given groups G and H we form the group G\times H as the set of pairs (g,h) with g in G and h in H. We compose them term-by-term: (g_1,h_1)(g_2,h_2)=(g_1g_2,h_1h_2). It can be verified that this gives us a group.

There’s a very interesting property about this group. It comes equipped with two homomorphisms, \pi_G and \pi_H, the “projections” of G\times H onto G and H, respectively. As one might expect, \pi_G(g,h)=g, and similarly for \pi_H. Even better, let’s consider any other group X with homomorphisms f_G:X\rightarrow G and f_H:X\rightarrow H. There is a unique homomorphism f_G\times f_H:X\rightarrow G\times H — defined by f_G\times f_H(x)=(f_G(x),f_H(x)) — so that \pi_G(f_G\times f_H(x))=f_G(x) and \pi_H(f_G\times f_H(x))=f_H(x). Here’s the picture.

Universal Property of Products

The vertical arrow from X to G\times H is f_G\times f_H, and I assert that that’s the only homomorphism from X to G\times H so that both paths from X to G are the same, as are both paths from X to H. When we draw a diagram like this with groups on the points and homomorphisms for arrows, we say that the diagram “commutes” if any two paths joining the same point give the same homomorphism between those two groups.

To restate it again, G\times H has homomorphisms to G and H, and any other group X with a pair of homomorphisms to G and H has a unique homomorphism from X to G\times H so that the above diagram commutes. This uniqueness means that has this property is unique up to isomorphism.

Let’s say two groups P_1 and P_2 have this product property. That is, each has given homomorphisms to G and H, and given any other group with a pair of homomorphisms there is a unique homomorphism to P_1 and one to P_2 that make the diagrams commute (with P_1 or P_2 in the place of G\times H). Then from the P_1 diagram with P_2 in place of X we get a unique homomorphism f_1:P_2\rightarrow P_1. On the other hand, from the P_2 diagram with P_1 in place of X, we get a unique homomorphism f_2:P_1\rightarrow P_2. Putting these two together we get homomorphisms f_1f_2:P_2\rightarrow P_2 and f_2f_1:P_1\rightarrow P_1.

Now if we think of the diagram for P_1 with P_1 itself in place of X, we see that there’s a unique homomorphism from P_1 to itself making the diagram commute. We just made one called f_2f_1, but the identity homomorphism on P_1 also works, so they must be the same! Similarly, f_1f_2 must be the identity on P_2, so f_1 and f_2 are inverses of each other, and P_1 and P_2 are isomorphic!

So let’s look back at this whole thing again. I take two groups G and H, and I want a new group G\times H that has homomorphisms to G and H and so any other such group with two homomorphisms has a unique homomorphism to G\times H. Any two groups satisfying this property are isomorphic, so if we can find any group satisfying this property we know that any other one will be essentially the same. The group structure we define on the Cartesian product of the sets G and H satisfies just such a property, so we call it the direct product of the two groups.

This method of defining things is called a “universal property”. The argument I gave to show that the product is essentially unique works for any such definition, so things defined to satisfy universal properties are unique (up to isomorphism) if they actually exist at all. This is a viewpoint on group theory that often gets left out of basic treatments of the subject, but one that I feel gets right to the heart of why the theory behaves the way it does. We’ll definitely be seeing more of it.

February 27, 2007 - Posted by | Algebra, Group theory, Structure of Groups, Universal Properties

13 Comments »

  1. […] course, by the exact same sort of argument I gave when discussing direct products of groups, once we have a universal property any two things satisfying that property are isomorphic. This is […]

    Pingback by Natural Numbers « The Unapologetic Mathematician | March 5, 2007 | Reply

  2. […] Exact Sequences and Semidirect Products The direct product of two groups provides a special sort of short exact sequence. We know that there is a surjection , […]

    Pingback by Split Exact Sequences and Semidirect Products « The Unapologetic Mathematician | March 8, 2007 | Reply

  3. […] sums of Abelian groups Let’s go back to direct products and free products of groups and consider them just in the context of abelian […]

    Pingback by Direct sums of Abelian groups « The Unapologetic Mathematician | April 12, 2007 | Reply

  4. […] First Isomorphism theorems, for example. I’ll also show how, in the language of categories, direct products of groups are like greatest lower […]

    Pingback by Future directions « The Unapologetic Mathematician | May 20, 2007 | Reply

  5. […] categories and we define the product category like we did the direct product of groups and other such algebraic gadgets. We need a category with “projection functors” and […]

    Pingback by Product categories « The Unapologetic Mathematician | June 1, 2007 | Reply

  6. I wonder if universal properties could be made easier for beginners to grasp if more of the structure of the concept was displayed directly in the language. For example, an attempted definition of direct product:

    H has the direct product property ‘flabbily’ for F, G via functions f, g iff f is a homomorphism from H to F and g is a homomorphsim from H to G.

    H is has the direct product property universally for F, G via functions f, g if it does so flabbily, and for any other H', f', g' which also does so flabbily, there is a unique homomorphism h:H'\rightarrow H such that f'=fh and g'=gh.

    H, f, g are a direct product of F, G if H has the direct product universally for F, G via f, g

    Grammatically, the first part (the ‘flabby’ version of the property) is supposed to be a predicate with four arguments, corresponding to various bits of the cone construction: the apex, which is involved in the unique arrow, the ingredients (objects and arrows) of the base, the property that characterizes how these ingredients and the `via’ arrows are supposed to be related, and the via-arrows that connect the apex to the ingredient objects.

    Then a lot of ‘verb-phrase anaphora’ is used in defining the strict/universal part, in order to gammatically display the fact that the concepts from the flabby part are being re-used.

    Maybe this is too cumbersome to be useful to beginners, but, speaking for myself, I was never able to understand the usual verbiage concerning universal properties until I sort of understood how cones/limits worked. So the idea here is to express the structure of the cone (and cocone) ideas more directly than usual in the language, without dragging in as much abstraction.

    Comment by MathOutsider | October 9, 2007 | Reply

  7. Well, MO, that’s an idea that actually shows up in some circles. Witness the term “weak Natural Numbers Object” in topos theory. Unfortunately, “weak” already tends to mean something else in other areas of category theory…

    Comment by John Armstrong | October 9, 2007 | Reply

  8. That’s why I chose ‘flabbily’ – doesn’t sound very nice but everything else I could think of that sounded better already had some other meanings that even I have encountered, although not necessarily understood.

    Comment by MathOutsider | October 10, 2007 | Reply

  9. Maybe smoother reformulation of 6, which is supposed to follow the standard formulation a bit more closely:

    C, f, g is a flabby product of A, B iff f:C\rightarrow A, g:C\rightarrow A.

    C, f, g is a (real/universal) product of A, B if it is a flabby one such that for any (possibly other) flabby one C', f', g' there is a unique h:C'\rightarrow C s.t. f'=fh, g'=gh.

    ‘wannabe’ would perhaps be an alternative to ‘flabby’. Well only the actual beginners can judge whether something like this is helpful, assuming it isn’t actively misleading.

    Comment by MathOutsider | October 10, 2007 | Reply

  10. The (co-)universal property behind commutator subgroups in the above tediously explicit format:

    A, f is a wannabe ‘abelianator’ of group G if A is an abelian group and the image of G under h.

    A, f is a co-universal abelianator of group G if it is a wannabe, and, for any other such wannabe A',f', there is a unique group homorphism h:A\rightarrow A' such that f'=hf.

    Putting it in this form caused me to see that the relevant property was co-universal rather than just universal, tho presumably people with more talent or experience would see this immediately.

    Reformulating in terms of the subgroup embeddings rather than homomorphisms between quotients, things get rearranged a bit:

    C,\iota is a wannabe-commutator of G if \iota is an injection of C into G and G/C is commutative.

    C, \iota is a (co?)universal commutator of G if it is a wannabe, and for any other such wannabe C',\iota', there is a unique h:C\rightarrow C' such that \iota=\iota' h.

    Here general format of a (co-)cone isn’t being followed, since the universal object’s arrows are factoring thru the wannabe’s rather than vice-versa. Don’t know what the terminology for this is.

    Comment by MathOutsider | October 12, 2007 | Reply

  11. Well, no. In that case it’s not really a cone. It’s a universal object in some category — one which you described correctly — but not a category of cones.

    Limits and colimits are terminal and initial objects in categories of cones and cocones, but not all universal properties comes from these sorts of categories.

    Comment by John Armstrong | October 12, 2007 | Reply

  12. […] elements altogether and draw this diagram: What does this mean? Well, it’s like the diagram I drew for products of groups. The product of and is a set with functions and so that for any other set with functions to […]

    Pingback by Products and Coproducts « The Unapologetic Mathematician | December 5, 2007 | Reply

  13. […] Product Groups An important construction for groups is their direct product. Given two groups and we take the cartesian product of their underlying sets and put a group […]

    Pingback by Representing Product Groups « The Unapologetic Mathematician | November 1, 2010 | Reply


Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s

%d bloggers like this: