Direct Products of Groups
There are two sorts of products on groups that I’d like to discuss. Today I’ll talk about direct products.
The direct product says that we can take two groups, form the Cartesian product of their sets, and put the structure of a group on that. Given groups and
we form the group
as the set of pairs
with
in
and
in
. We compose them term-by-term:
. It can be verified that this gives us a group.
There’s a very interesting property about this group. It comes equipped with two homomorphisms, and
, the “projections” of
onto
and
, respectively. As one might expect,
, and similarly for
. Even better, let’s consider any other group
with homomorphisms
and
. There is a unique homomorphism
— defined by
— so that
and
. Here’s the picture.
The vertical arrow from to
is
, and I assert that that’s the only homomorphism from
to
so that both paths from
to
are the same, as are both paths from
to
. When we draw a diagram like this with groups on the points and homomorphisms for arrows, we say that the diagram “commutes” if any two paths joining the same point give the same homomorphism between those two groups.
To restate it again, has homomorphisms to
and
, and any other group
with a pair of homomorphisms to
and
has a unique homomorphism from
to
so that the above diagram commutes. This uniqueness means that has this property is unique up to isomorphism.
Let’s say two groups and
have this product property. That is, each has given homomorphisms to
and
, and given any other group with a pair of homomorphisms there is a unique homomorphism to
and one to
that make the diagrams commute (with
or
in the place of
). Then from the
diagram with
in place of
we get a unique homomorphism
. On the other hand, from the
diagram with
in place of
, we get a unique homomorphism
. Putting these two together we get homomorphisms
and
.
Now if we think of the diagram for with
itself in place of
, we see that there’s a unique homomorphism from
to itself making the diagram commute. We just made one called
, but the identity homomorphism on
also works, so they must be the same! Similarly,
must be the identity on
, so
and
are inverses of each other, and
and
are isomorphic!
So let’s look back at this whole thing again. I take two groups and
, and I want a new group
that has homomorphisms to
and
and so any other such group with two homomorphisms has a unique homomorphism to
. Any two groups satisfying this property are isomorphic, so if we can find any group satisfying this property we know that any other one will be essentially the same. The group structure we define on the Cartesian product of the sets
and
satisfies just such a property, so we call it the direct product of the two groups.
This method of defining things is called a “universal property”. The argument I gave to show that the product is essentially unique works for any such definition, so things defined to satisfy universal properties are unique (up to isomorphism) if they actually exist at all. This is a viewpoint on group theory that often gets left out of basic treatments of the subject, but one that I feel gets right to the heart of why the theory behaves the way it does. We’ll definitely be seeing more of it.
[…] course, by the exact same sort of argument I gave when discussing direct products of groups, once we have a universal property any two things satisfying that property are isomorphic. This is […]
Pingback by Natural Numbers « The Unapologetic Mathematician | March 5, 2007 |
[…] Exact Sequences and Semidirect Products The direct product of two groups provides a special sort of short exact sequence. We know that there is a surjection , […]
Pingback by Split Exact Sequences and Semidirect Products « The Unapologetic Mathematician | March 8, 2007 |
[…] sums of Abelian groups Let’s go back to direct products and free products of groups and consider them just in the context of abelian […]
Pingback by Direct sums of Abelian groups « The Unapologetic Mathematician | April 12, 2007 |
[…] First Isomorphism theorems, for example. I’ll also show how, in the language of categories, direct products of groups are like greatest lower […]
Pingback by Future directions « The Unapologetic Mathematician | May 20, 2007 |
[…] categories and we define the product category like we did the direct product of groups and other such algebraic gadgets. We need a category with “projection functors” and […]
Pingback by Product categories « The Unapologetic Mathematician | June 1, 2007 |
I wonder if universal properties could be made easier for beginners to grasp if more of the structure of the concept was displayed directly in the language. For example, an attempted definition of direct product:
Grammatically, the first part (the ‘flabby’ version of the property) is supposed to be a predicate with four arguments, corresponding to various bits of the cone construction: the apex, which is involved in the unique arrow, the ingredients (objects and arrows) of the base, the property that characterizes how these ingredients and the `via’ arrows are supposed to be related, and the via-arrows that connect the apex to the ingredient objects.
Then a lot of ‘verb-phrase anaphora’ is used in defining the strict/universal part, in order to gammatically display the fact that the concepts from the flabby part are being re-used.
Maybe this is too cumbersome to be useful to beginners, but, speaking for myself, I was never able to understand the usual verbiage concerning universal properties until I sort of understood how cones/limits worked. So the idea here is to express the structure of the cone (and cocone) ideas more directly than usual in the language, without dragging in as much abstraction.
Well, MO, that’s an idea that actually shows up in some circles. Witness the term “weak Natural Numbers Object” in topos theory. Unfortunately, “weak” already tends to mean something else in other areas of category theory…
That’s why I chose ‘flabbily’ – doesn’t sound very nice but everything else I could think of that sounded better already had some other meanings that even I have encountered, although not necessarily understood.
Maybe smoother reformulation of 6, which is supposed to follow the standard formulation a bit more closely:
‘wannabe’ would perhaps be an alternative to ‘flabby’. Well only the actual beginners can judge whether something like this is helpful, assuming it isn’t actively misleading.
The (co-)universal property behind commutator subgroups in the above tediously explicit format:
Putting it in this form caused me to see that the relevant property was co-universal rather than just universal, tho presumably people with more talent or experience would see this immediately.
Reformulating in terms of the subgroup embeddings rather than homomorphisms between quotients, things get rearranged a bit:
Here general format of a (co-)cone isn’t being followed, since the universal object’s arrows are factoring thru the wannabe’s rather than vice-versa. Don’t know what the terminology for this is.
Well, no. In that case it’s not really a cone. It’s a universal object in some category — one which you described correctly — but not a category of cones.
Limits and colimits are terminal and initial objects in categories of cones and cocones, but not all universal properties comes from these sorts of categories.
[…] elements altogether and draw this diagram: What does this mean? Well, it’s like the diagram I drew for products of groups. The product of and is a set with functions and so that for any other set with functions to […]
Pingback by Products and Coproducts « The Unapologetic Mathematician | December 5, 2007 |
[…] Product Groups An important construction for groups is their direct product. Given two groups and we take the cartesian product of their underlying sets and put a group […]
Pingback by Representing Product Groups « The Unapologetic Mathematician | November 1, 2010 |