Representations and Universals and Colimits (oh, my!)
Let’s look at universal arrows a bit more closely. If we have a functor , an object
, and a universal arrow
, then we can take any arrow
and form the composition
. The universal condition says that to every arrow
corresponds a unique
so that
. That is, there is a bijection
for every
.
It’s even better than that, though: these bijections commute with arrows in . That is, if we have
then the naturality condition
holds for all
. This makes the
into the components of a natural isomorphism
. That is, a universal arrow from
to
is a representation of the functor
.
Conversely, let’s say we have a representable functor , with representation
. Yoneda’s lemma tells us that this natural transformation corresponds to a unique element of
, which as usual we think of as an arrow
. So a representation of a functor is a universal arrow in
.
So, representations of functors are the same as universal arrows. Colimits are special kinds of universal arrows, and since a universal arrow is an initial object in an apropriate comma category it is a colimit. Representations are universals are colimits.
If we swap the category for the dual category
, we change limits into colimits, couniversals into universals, and contravariant representations into covariant ones. All the reasoning above applies just as well to
. Thus, we see that in
representations of contravariant functors are couniversals are limits.
There’s actually yet another concept yet to work into this story, but I’m going to take a break from it to flesh out another area of category theory for a while.
No comments yet.
Leave a Reply