Topologies as Categories
Okay, so we’ve defined a topology on a set . But we also love categories, so we want to see this in terms of categories. And, indeed, every topology is a category!
First, remember that the collection of subsets of , like the collection of subobjects on an object in any category, is partially ordered by inclusion. And since every partially ordered set is a category, so is the collection of subsets of
.
In fact, it’s a lattice, since we can use union and intersection as our join and meet, respectively. When we say that a poset has pairwise least upper bounds it’s the same as saying when we consider it as a category it has finite coproducts, and similarly pairwise greatest lower bounds are the same as finite products. But here we can actually take the union or intersection of any collection of subsets and get a subset, so we have all products and coproducts. In the language of posets, we have a “complete lattice”.
So now we want to talk about topologies. A topology is just a collection of the subsets that’s closed under finite intersections and arbitrary unions. We can use the same order (inclusion of subsets) to make a topology into a partially-ordered set. In the language of posets, the requirements are that we have a sublattice (finite meets and joins, along with the same top and bottom element) with arbitrary meets — the topology contains the least upper bound of any collection of its elements.
And now we translate the partial order language into category theory. A topology is a subcategory of the category of subsets of with finite products and all coproducts. That is, we have an arrow from the object
to the object
if and only if
as subsets of
. Given any finite collection
of objects we have their product
, and given any collection
of objects we have their coproduct
. In particular we have the empty product — the terminal object
— and we have the empty coproduct — the initial object
. And all the arrows in our category just tell us how various open sets sit inside other open sets. Neat!