The Branching Rule, Part 3
“Part 3”? Didn’t we just finish proving the branching rule? Well, yes, but there’s another part we haven’t mentioned yet. Not only does the branching rule tell us how representations of decompose when they’re restricted to
, it also tells us how representations of
decompose when they’re induced to
.
Now that we have the first statement of the branching rule down, proving the other one is fairly straightforward: it’s a consequence of Frobenius reciprocity. Indeed, the branching rule tells us that
That is, there is one copy of inside
(considered as an
-module) if
comes from
by removing an inner corner, and there are no copies otherwise.
So let’s try to calculate the multiplicity of in the induced module
:
Taking dimensions, we find
since if comes from
by removing an inner corner, then
comes from
by adding an outer corner.
We conclude that
which is the other half of the branching rule.
The Branching Rule, Part 2
We pick up our proof of the branching rule. We have a partition with inner corners in rows
. The partitions we get by removing each of the inner corner
is
. If the tableau
(or the tabloid
has its
in row
, then
(or
) is the result of removing that
.
We’re looking for a chain of subspaces
such that as
-modules. I say that we can define
to be the subspace of
spanned by the standard polytabloids
where the
shows up in row
or above in
.
For each , define the map
by removing an
in row
. That is, if
latex M^\lambda$ has its
in row
, set
; otherwise set
. These are all homomorphisms of
-modules, since the action of
always leaves the
in the same row, and so it commutes with removing an
from row
.
Similarly, I say that if
is in row
of
, and we get
if it’s in row
with
. Indeed if
shows up above row
, then since it’s the bottommost entry in its column that column can have no entries at all in row
. Thus as we use
to shuffle the columns, all of the tabloids that show up in
will be sent to zero by
. Similar considerations show that if
is in row
, then of all the tabloids that show up in
, only those leaving
in that row are not sent to zero by
. The permutations in
leaving
fixed are, of course, exactly those in
, and our assertion holds.
Now, since each standard polytabloid comes from some polytabloid
, we see they’re all in the image of
. Further, these
all have their
s in row
, so they’re all in
. That is,
. On the other hand, if
has its
above row
, then
, and so
.
So now we’ve got a longer chain of subspaces:
But we also know that
So the steps from to
give us all the
as we add up dimensions. Comparing to the formula we’re categorifying, we see that this accounts for all of
. And so there are no dimensions left for the steps from
to
, and these containments must actually be equalities!
And thus
as asserted. The branching rule then follows.
The Branching Rule, Part 1
We want to “categorify” the relation we came up with last time:
That is, we want to replace these numbers with objects of a category, replace the sum with a direct sum, and replace the equation with a natural isomorphism.
It should be clear that an obvious choice for the objects is to replace with the Specht module
, since we’ve seen that
. But what category are they in? On the left side,
is an
-module, but on the right side all the
are
-modules. Our solution is to restrict
, suggesting the isomorphism
This tells us what happens to any of the Specht modules as we restrict it to a smaller symmetric group. As a side note, it doesn’t really matter which we use, since they’re all conjugate to each other inside
. So we’ll just use the one that permutes all the numbers but
.
Anyway, say the inner corners of occur in the rows
, and of course they must occur at the ends of these rows. For each one, we’ll write
for the partition that comes from removing that inner corner. Similarly, if
is a standard tableau with
in the
th row, we write
for the (standard) tableau with
removed. And the same goes for the standard tabloids
and
.
Our method will be to find a tower of subspaces
so that at each step we have as
-modules. Then we can see that
And similarly we find , and step by step we go until we find the proposed isomorphism. The construction itself will be presented next time.
Inner and Outer Corners
The next thing we need to take note of it the idea of an “inner corner” and an “outer corner” of a Ferrers diagram, and thus of a partition.
An inner corner of a Ferrers diagram is a cell that, if it’s removed, the rest of the diagram is still the Ferrers diagram of a partition. It must be the rightmost cell in its row, and the bottommost cell in its column. Similarly, an outer corner is one that, if it’s added to the diagram, the result is still the Ferrers diagram of a partition. This is a little more subtle: it must be just to the right of the end of a row, and just below the bottom of a column.
As an example, consider the partition , with Ferrers diagram
We highlight the inner corners by shrinking them, and mark the outer corners with circles:
That is, there are three ways we could remove a cell and still have the Ferrers diagram of a partition:
And there are four ways that we could add a cell and still have the Ferrers diagram of a partition:
If the first partition is , we write a generic partition that comes from removing a single inner corner by
. Similarly, we write a generic partition that comes from adding a single outer corner by
. In our case, if
, then the three possible
partitions are
,
, and
, while the four possible
partitions are
,
,
, and
.
Now, as a quick use of this concept, think about how to fill a Ferrers diagram to make a standard Young tableau. It should be clear that since is the largest entry in the tableau, it must be in the rightmost cell of its row and the bottommost cell of its column in order for the tableau to be standard. Thus
must occur in an inner corner. This means that we can describe any standard tableau by picking which inner corner contains
, removing that corner, and filling the rest with a standard tableau with
entries. Thus, the number of standard
-tableaux is the sum of all the standard
-tableaux:
Young’s Natural Representation
Now that we have a canonical basis for our Specht modules composed of standard polytabloids it gives us a matrix representation of for each
. We really only need to come up with matrices for the swaps
, for
, since these generate the whole symmetric group.
When we calculate the action of the swap on a polytabloid associated with a standard Young tableau
, there are three possibilities. Either
and
are in the same column of
, they’re in the same row of
, or they’re not in the same row or column of
.
The first case is easy. If and
are in the same column of
, then
, and thus
.
The third case isn’t much harder, although it’s subtler. I say that if and
share neither a row nor a column, then
is again standard. Indeed, swapping the two can’t introduce either a row or a column descent. The entries to the left of and above
are all less than
, and none of them are
, so they’re all less than
as well. Similarly, all the entries to the right of and below
are greater than
, and none of them are
, so they’re all greater than
as well.
Where things get complicated is when and
share a row. But then they have to be next to each other, and the swap introduces a row descent between them. We can then use our Garnir elements to write this polytabloid in terms of standard ones.
Let’s work this out explicitly for the Specht module , which should give us our well-known two-dimensional representation of
. The basis consists of the polytabloids associated to these two tableaux:
We need to come up with matrices for the two swaps and
. And the second one is easy: it just swaps these two tableaux! Thus we get the matrix
The action of on the second standard tableau is similarly easy. Since
and
are in the same column, the swap acts by multiplying by
. Thus we can write down a column of the matrix
As for the action on the first tableau, the swap induces a row descent. We use a Garnir element to straighten it out. With the same abuse of notation as last time, we write
and so we can fill in the other column:
From here we can write all the other matrices in the representation as products of these two.
“Straightening” a Polytabloid
Let’s look at one example of “straightening” out a polytabloid to show it’s in the span of the standard polytabloids, using the Garnir elements.
We’ll start with one we’ve already partially worked out:
Now, it’s slightly abusive to the notation, but we’ll just write a tableau and know that we actually mean the polytabloid
in our linear combinations. Using this, we’ve seen that we can write
Now, by the way we’ve selected our Garnir elements, we know that none of these can have any column descents. And we also know that they can’t have a row descent in the same place did. Indeed, the only three that have a row descent all have it between the second and third entries of the first row. So now let’s look at
We can write down another table, just like before:
which lets us write
Similarly we can write
and
Putting these all together, we conclude that
All of these tabloids are standard, and so we see that our original — nonstandard — is in the span of the standard polytabloids.
Standard Polytabloids Span Specht Modules
We defined the Specht module as the subspace of the Young tabloid module
spanned by polytabloids of shape
. But these polytabloids are not independent. We’ve seen that standard polytabloids are independent, and it turns out that they also span. That is, they provide an explicit basis for the Specht module
.
Anyway, first off we can take care of all the where the columns of
don’t increase down the column. Indeed, if
stabilizes the columns of
, then
where we’ve used the sign lemma. So any two polytabloids coming from tableaux in the same column equivalence class are scalar multiples of each other. We’ve just cut our spanning set down from one element for each tableau to one for each column equivalence class of tableaux.
To deal with column equivalence classes, start with the tableau that we get by filling in the shape with the numbers
to
in order down the first column, then the second, and so on. This is the maximum element in the column dominance order, and it’s standard. Given any other tableau
, we assume that every tableau
with
is already in the span of the standard polytabloids. This is an inductive hypothesis, and the base case is taken care of by the maximum tabloid
.
If is itself standard, we’re done, since it’s obviously in the span of the standard polytabloids. If not, there must be a row descent — we’ve ruled out column descents already — and so we can pick our Garnir element to write
as the sum of a bunch of other polytabloids
, where
in the column dominance order. But by our inductive hypothesis, all these
are in the span of the standard polytabloids, and thus
is as well.
As an immediate consequence, we conclude that , where
is the number of standard tableaux of shape
. Further, since we know from our decomposition of the left regular representation that each irreducible representation of
shows up in
with a multiplicity equal to its dimension, we can write
Taking dimensions on both sides we find
Properties of Garnir Elements from Tableaux 2
When we pick a tableau with a certain row descent and use it to pick sets
and
, as we’ve done, the resulting Garnir element is a sum of a bunch of tabloids coming from a bunch of tableaux. I say that the column tabloid
corresponding to the original tableau is dominated by all the other tabloids, using the column dominance order.
Indeed, when considering column tabloids we can rearrange the entries within columns freely, so we may assume that they’re always increasing down the columns. If we have our row descent in row , we can label the entries in the left column by
s and those in the right column by
s. Our tabloid then looks — in these two columns, at least — something like
We see our sets and
. The permutations in the transversal that we use to construct our Garnir element work by moving swapping some of the
s with some of the
s. But since all that
s are smaller than all the
s, while they occur in a row further to the right, the dominance lemma for column tabloids tells us that any such swap can only move the tabloid up in the dominance order.
It is in this sense that the Garnir element lets us replace a tabloid with a linear combination of other tabloids that are “more standard”. And it puts us within striking distance of our goal.
The Column Dominance Order
Okay, for the last couple posts I’ve talked about using Garnir elements to rewrite nonstandard polytabloids — those coming from tableaux containing “row descents” — in terms of “more standard” polytabloids. Finally, we’re going to define another partial order that will give some meaning to this language.
Given a tableau , consider the column stabilizer
, and use it to build the “column tabloid”
. This is defined just like our other tabloids, except by shuffling columns instead of rows.
For example, consider the tabloid
from which we get the column tabloid
And now we can define the dominance order on column tabloids just like the dominance order for row tabloids. Of course, in doing so we have to alter our definition of the dominance order on Ferrers diagrams to take columns into account instead of rows.
But one thing at least will make our life simpler: it should be clear that we still have a dominance lemma for column dominance. To be explicit: if , and
appears in a column to the right of
in the column tabloid
, then
dominates
in the column dominance order.
Properties of Garnir Elements from Tableaux 1
Pick a Young tableau , and sets
and
as we did last time. If there are more entries in
than there are in the
th column of
— the one containing
— then
. In particular, if we pick
and
by selecting a row descent, letting
be the entries below the left entry, and letting
be the entries above the right entry, then this situation will hold.
As a first step, I say that . That is, if we allow all the permutations of entries in these two sets (along with signs) then everything cancels out. Indeed, let
be any column-stabilizing permutation. Our hypothesis on the number of entries in
tells us that we must have some pair of
and
in the same row of
. Thus the swap
. The sign lemma then tells us that
. Since this is true for every summand
of
, it is true for
itself.
Now, our assertion is not that this is true for all of , but rather that it holds for our transversal
. We use the decomposition
This gives us a factorization
And so we conclude that .
But now we note that . So if
we use the sign lemma to conclude
Thus , and so
which can only happen if , as asserted.
This result will allow us to pick out a row descent in and write down a linear combination of polytabloids that lets us rewrite
in terms of other polytabloids. And it will turn out that all the other polytabloids will be “more standard” than
.