The Branching Rule, Part 2
We pick up our proof of the branching rule. We have a partition with inner corners in rows
. The partitions we get by removing each of the inner corner
is
. If the tableau
(or the tabloid
has its
in row
, then
(or
) is the result of removing that
.
We’re looking for a chain of subspaces
such that as
-modules. I say that we can define
to be the subspace of
spanned by the standard polytabloids
where the
shows up in row
or above in
.
For each , define the map
by removing an
in row
. That is, if
latex M^\lambda$ has its
in row
, set
; otherwise set
. These are all homomorphisms of
-modules, since the action of
always leaves the
in the same row, and so it commutes with removing an
from row
.
Similarly, I say that if
is in row
of
, and we get
if it’s in row
with
. Indeed if
shows up above row
, then since it’s the bottommost entry in its column that column can have no entries at all in row
. Thus as we use
to shuffle the columns, all of the tabloids that show up in
will be sent to zero by
. Similar considerations show that if
is in row
, then of all the tabloids that show up in
, only those leaving
in that row are not sent to zero by
. The permutations in
leaving
fixed are, of course, exactly those in
, and our assertion holds.
Now, since each standard polytabloid comes from some polytabloid
, we see they’re all in the image of
. Further, these
all have their
s in row
, so they’re all in
. That is,
. On the other hand, if
has its
above row
, then
, and so
.
So now we’ve got a longer chain of subspaces:
But we also know that
So the steps from to
give us all the
as we add up dimensions. Comparing to the formula we’re categorifying, we see that this accounts for all of
. And so there are no dimensions left for the steps from
to
, and these containments must actually be equalities!
And thus
as asserted. The branching rule then follows.
[…] 3″? Didn’t we just finish proving the branching rule? Well, yes, but there’s another part we haven’t mentioned yet. Not […]
Pingback by The Branching Rule, Part 3 « The Unapologetic Mathematician | January 31, 2011 |
Hi, I really like your proof where everything is explained so well. But I dont get why the V^(i) as you defined them here are S^(n-1) modules. I tried showing it and the actual point missing is that the map from S_{n-1} x V^(i) gives results in V^(i). I think i.e. linear combinations of the polytabloids you used for V^(i) do still have n in one of the required rows after a permutation of S_{n-1} was applied. But how can this be true for an arbitrary permutation?
Sorry, it’s been a long time since I looked at this (almost three years now), so I might be a little rusty. I think the problem might be that I’m asserting that the quotient space
is an $S_{n-1}$-module, not that
itself is. Does that help?
Hi, thanks a lot for your answer! But I think there I have the same problem since now I need that n stays in the same row…
What I wrote was wrong. Now I need that all n stay in their line or are in a higher one by considering only polytabloids where the n in t is in one special line.